Why Should We Cultivate Taste? Answers from Kant’s Early and Late Aesthetic Theory

Author:

Watkins Brian

Publisher

Palgrave Macmillan UK

Reference6 articles.

1. Alix Cohen makes a related point, showing that Kant thinks, in the Observations, that sympathy and honor ensure the survival of the human species. See Alix Cohen, “Kant’s ‘Curious Catalogue of Human Frailties’ and the Great Portrait of Nature,” in Kant’s “Observations” and “Remarks”: A Critical Guide, ed. Susan Meld Shell and Richard Velkley (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 144–62.

2. On this point, see Paul Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Taste (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979), 16–19. Kant seems to have believed that there were no a priori principles of taste even up to the Critique of Pure Reason, published in 1781. There, he maintains that “the putative rules or criteria [of taste] are merely empirical as far as their sources are concerned, and can therefore never serve as a priori rules according to which our judgment of taste must be directed, rather the latter constitutes the genuine touchstone of the correctness of the former” (A21n/B35n). To be clear, although Kant comes to believe in the Critique of the Power of Judgment that we can justify judgments of taste by reference to an a priori principle, he also claims that this principle is accessible only through feeling. So, Kant would still consider what passed for “rules or criteria of taste” in the aesthetics textbooks of the time as nothing more than empirical generalizations, which in the best case could be based on universally valid judgments of taste. See, for example, Kant’s dismissal of Gotthold Ephraim Lessing’s and Charles Batteux’s attempts to “prove” the beauty of an object (CJ 5:284).

3. For a more detailed analysis of Kant’s claim that taste must be devoid of all interest, see Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Taste, 167–206; and Paul Guyer, Kant and the Experience of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 48–130.

4. This point has been discussed in detail by many commentators. See, for example, Klaus Düsing, “Beauty as the Transition from Nature to Freedom in Kant’s Critique of Judgment,” Noûs 24, no. 1 (March 1990): 84. G. Felicitas Munzel also discusses the relationship between aesthetic and moral education. See G. Felicitas Munzel, Kant’s Conception of Moral Character: The “Critical” Link of Morality, Anthropology, and Reflective Judgment (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 296–313. Salim Kemal also provides a detailed discussion of the role that fine art in particular plays in facilitating our transition to morality. He explains that the purpose of developing one’s taste is to establish a unity or balance between reason and feeling in an individual human for the sake of attaining the highest good.

5. See Salim Kemal, Kant and Fine Art: An Essay on Kant and the Philosophy of Fine Art and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 84–98. See also Guyer, Kant and the Experience of Freedom, 34–35.

Cited by 1 articles. 订阅此论文施引文献 订阅此论文施引文献,注册后可以免费订阅5篇论文的施引文献,订阅后可以查看论文全部施引文献

同舟云学术

1.学者识别学者识别

2.学术分析学术分析

3.人才评估人才评估

"同舟云学术"是以全球学者为主线,采集、加工和组织学术论文而形成的新型学术文献查询和分析系统,可以对全球学者进行文献检索和人才价值评估。用户可以通过关注某些学科领域的顶尖人物而持续追踪该领域的学科进展和研究前沿。经过近期的数据扩容,当前同舟云学术共收录了国内外主流学术期刊6万余种,收集的期刊论文及会议论文总量共计约1.5亿篇,并以每天添加12000余篇中外论文的速度递增。我们也可以为用户提供个性化、定制化的学者数据。欢迎来电咨询!咨询电话:010-8811{复制后删除}0370

www.globalauthorid.com

TOP

Copyright © 2019-2024 北京同舟云网络信息技术有限公司
京公网安备11010802033243号  京ICP备18003416号-3