Affiliation:
1. PHD STUDENT, UNIVERSITY OF zurich
Abstract
In this paper, I argue that Alfred Mele’s conception of self-deception is such that it always fulfils the reasons-responsiveness condition for doxastic responsibility. This is because self-deceptive mechanisms of belief formation are such that the kind of beliefs they bring about are the kind of beliefs that fulfil the criteria for doxastic responsibility from epistemic reasons responsiveness. I explain why in this paper. Mele describes the relation of the subject to the evidence as a biased relation. The subject does not simply believe on the basis of evidence, but on the basis of manipulated evidence. Mele puts forward four ways in which the subject does this. The subject could misinterpret positively or negatively, selectively focus, or gather evidence. Through these ways of manipulation, the evidence is framed such that the final product constitutes evidence on the basis of which the subject may believe a proposition that fits that subject’s desire that P. Whichever form of manipulation the subject uses, the evidence against P must be neutralized in one way or another. Successful neutralization of the evidence requires the ability to recognize what the evidence supports and the ability to react to it. These abilities consist precisely in the two parts of the reasons-responsiveness condition, reasons receptivity and reasons reactivity. In that sense, self-deceptive beliefs always fulfil the reasons-responsiveness condition for doxastic responsibility. However, given that reasons responsiveness is only a necessary condition for doxastic responsibility, this does not mean that self-deceived subjects are always responsible for their belief.
Reference23 articles.
1. Alston, William, “The Deontological Conception of Epistemic Justification,” Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 2, 1988, p. 257-299.
2. DeWeese-Boyd, Ian, “Taking Care: Self-Deception, Culpability and Control,” Teorema, vol. 23, no. 3, 2007, p. 161-176.
3. Fischer, John M., and Mark Ravizza, Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1998.
4. Ginet, Carl, “Working with Fischer and Ravizza’s Account of Moral Responsibility,” Journal of Ethics, vol. 10, no. 3, 2005, p. 229-253.
5. Hieronymi, Pamela, “Responsibility for Believing,” Synthese, vol. 161, no. 3, 2008, p. 357-373.
Cited by
1 articles.
订阅此论文施引文献
订阅此论文施引文献,注册后可以免费订阅5篇论文的施引文献,订阅后可以查看论文全部施引文献