How presuppositions and illocutionary force become components of sense: some implications from the analysis of fictitious names in Frege’s philosophy

Author:

Mikirtumov Ivan B.1

Affiliation:

1. Russian Society for the History and Philosophy of Science

Abstract

Frege's fictitious names possess meaning but lack denotation. Both these names and the sentences containing them are deemed fictitious. Since any proper name can potentially refer to an imaginary entity, it is crucial to consider the speaker's intention. When making a statement, the speaker may refer to the real or the imaginary. In the latter case, the thought cannot be explicitly expressed, and consequently, denotation cannot be reached. In Frege's framework, fictional thoughts hold little significance for decision-making and actions. There­fore, we consistently seek to discern whether the discourse pertains to the real or the imagi­nary. To make this knowledge accessible, it must be incorporated into the content of a sen­tence, effectively becoming a thought. However, not every statement expresses a thought, even if it conforms to the structure of a sentence. I will now elucidate three intensionalization pro­cedures that Frege proposes for constructing a sentence that expresses a thought, even if cer­tain components within it lack denotation: the articulation of a naming relation, the formula­tion of a propositional attitude of intention, and the formulation of a propositional attitude that conveys a metafictional context. Through these methods, the speaker's intent to indicate a real or fictional object becomes a constituent of thought, i. e., the sense of the sentence. Fic­tions themselves become components of thought when they are found in an indirect context, wherein their sense serves as their denotation. When considered independently, the sense of a proper noun is an entity with a parameter that acquires a value in the specific situation where the name is employed by a particular speaker. Frege's foundational concepts are juxtaposed with certain aspects of Aristotle and Leibniz's doctrines.

Publisher

Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University

Subject

Literature and Literary Theory,Language and Linguistics

Reference46 articles.

1. Aristotle, 1937. O chastyakh zhivotnykh [About the parts of animals]. Translated by V. P. Karpov. Moscow (in Russ.).

2. Aristotle, 1976. Metaphysics. In: Aristotel'. Sobranie sochinenii v 4-kh tomakh [Aris­totle. Collected works in 4 volumes]. Vol. 1. Translated by A. V. Kubitski. Moscow, pp. 63—367 (in Russ.).

3. Aristotle, 1978a. Categories. In: Aristotel'. Sobranie sochinenii v 4-kh tomakh [Aristo­tle. Collected works in 4 volumes]. Vol. 2. Translated by A. V. Kubitski. Moscow, pp. 51—89 (in Russ.).

4. Aristotle, 1978b. About interpretation. In: Aristotel'. Sobranie sochinenii v 4-kh tomakh [Aristotle. Collected works in 4 volumes]. Vol. 2. Translated by E. V. Radlov. Moscow, pp. 91—115 (in Russ.).

5. Aristotle, 1978c. Second analytics. In: Aristotel'. Sobranie sochinenii v 4-kh tomakh [Aristotle. Collected works in 4 volumes]. Vol. 2. Translated by B. A. Focht. Moscow, pp. 255—345 (in Russ.).

同舟云学术

1.学者识别学者识别

2.学术分析学术分析

3.人才评估人才评估

"同舟云学术"是以全球学者为主线,采集、加工和组织学术论文而形成的新型学术文献查询和分析系统,可以对全球学者进行文献检索和人才价值评估。用户可以通过关注某些学科领域的顶尖人物而持续追踪该领域的学科进展和研究前沿。经过近期的数据扩容,当前同舟云学术共收录了国内外主流学术期刊6万余种,收集的期刊论文及会议论文总量共计约1.5亿篇,并以每天添加12000余篇中外论文的速度递增。我们也可以为用户提供个性化、定制化的学者数据。欢迎来电咨询!咨询电话:010-8811{复制后删除}0370

www.globalauthorid.com

TOP

Copyright © 2019-2024 北京同舟云网络信息技术有限公司
京公网安备11010802033243号  京ICP备18003416号-3