Affiliation:
1. University of South Alabama Department of Philosophy Mobile USA
Abstract
Abstract
Scholars have often thought that a monistic reading of Aristotle’s definition of the human good – in particular, one on which “best and most teleios virtue” (Nicomachean Ethics I 7, 1098a17–18) refers to theoretical wisdom – cannot follow from the premises of the ergon argument. I explain how a monistic reading can follow from the premises, and I argue that this interpretation gives the correct rationale for Aristotle’s definition. I then explain that even though the best and most teleios virtue must be a single virtue, that virtue could in principle be a whole virtue that arises from the combination of all the others (and this is what kalokagathia seems to be in the Eudemian Ethics). I also clarify that the definition of the human good aims at capturing the nature of human eudaimonia only in its primary case.
Reference66 articles.
1. Achtenberg, D. 1989. “The Role of the Ergon Argument in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics”. Ancient Philosophy 9(1), 37–47.
2. Ackrill, J. L. [1974]/1980. “Aristotle on Eudaimonia”. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. Ed. A. O. Rorty. Berkeley, CA. (Originally in the Proceedings of the British Academy 60).
3. Anagnostopoulos, A. 2017. “Change, Agency and the Incomplete in Aristotle”. Phronesis 6(2), 170–209.
4. Aquinas, T. 1969. Sententia Libri Ethicorum. Rome. Vol. 47 of T. Aquinas. (1882–ongoing). Opera Omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. Edita. Rome/Paris.
5. Aufderheide, J. 2015. “The Content of Happiness: A New Case for Theoria”. In The Highest Good in Aristotle and Kant. Ed. J. Aufderheide/R. Bader. Oxford, 36–59.
Cited by
1 articles.
订阅此论文施引文献
订阅此论文施引文献,注册后可以免费订阅5篇论文的施引文献,订阅后可以查看论文全部施引文献