Science, responsibility, and the philosophical imagination

Author:

Sample MatthewORCID

Abstract

AbstractIf we cannot define science using only analysis or description, then we must rely on imagination to provide us with suitable objects of philosophical inquiry. This process ties our intellectual findings to the particular ways in which we philosophers think about scientific practice and carve out a cognitive space between real world practice and conceptual abstraction. As an example, I consider Heather Douglas’s work on the responsibilities of scientists and document her implicit ideal of science, defined primarily as an epistemic practice. I then contrast her idealization of science with an alternative: “technoscience,” a heuristic concept used to describe nanotechnology, synthetic biology, and similar “Mode 2” forms of research. This comparison reveals that one’s preferred imaginary of science, even when inspired by real practices, has significant implications for the distribution of responsibility. Douglas’s account attributes moral obligations to scientists, while the imaginaries associated with “technoscience” and “Mode 2 science” spread responsibility across the network of practice. This dynamic between mind and social order, I argue, demands an ethics of imagination in which philosophers of science hold themselves accountable for their imaginaries. Extending analogous challenges from feminist philosophy and Mills’s. “Ideal Theory’ as Ideology,” I conclude that we ought to reflect on the idiosyncrasy of the philosophical imagination and consider how our idealizations of science, if widely held, would affect our communities and broader society.

Funder

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Universität Hannover

Publisher

Springer Science and Business Media LLC

Subject

General Social Sciences,Philosophy

Reference48 articles.

1. Bätge, D., Blundell, A., Gerr, W. D., Gotthelf, A., Hüsing, B., & Liesert, R. (2013). Well-ordered science in a not well-ordered society. In M. Kaiser & A. Seide (Eds.), Philip Kitcher: Pragmatic Naturalism (pp. 77–90). Frankfurt: Ontos.

2. Bensaude-Vincent, B. (2008). Technoscience and convergence: a transmutation of values? Summerschool on Ethics of Converging Technologies, Dormotel Vogelsberg, Omrod/Alsfeld, Germany. Retrieved January 23, 2022 from https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00350804.

3. Bensaude-Vincent, B., & Loeve, S. (2018). Toward a philosophy of technosciences. In S. Loeve, X. Guchet, & B. Bensaude-Vincent (Eds.), French Philosophy of Technology (pp. 169–186). Cham: Springer.

4. Bensaude-Vincent, B., Loeve, S., Nordmann, A., & Schwarz, A. (2011). Matters of interest: The objects of research in science and technoscience. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(2), 365–383.

5. Biddle, J. B., & Kukla, R. (2017). The geography of epistemic risk. In K. Elliot & T. Richards (Eds.), Exploring Inductive Risk: Case Studies of Values in Science (pp. 215–237). New York: Oxford University Press.

同舟云学术

1.学者识别学者识别

2.学术分析学术分析

3.人才评估人才评估

"同舟云学术"是以全球学者为主线,采集、加工和组织学术论文而形成的新型学术文献查询和分析系统,可以对全球学者进行文献检索和人才价值评估。用户可以通过关注某些学科领域的顶尖人物而持续追踪该领域的学科进展和研究前沿。经过近期的数据扩容,当前同舟云学术共收录了国内外主流学术期刊6万余种,收集的期刊论文及会议论文总量共计约1.5亿篇,并以每天添加12000余篇中外论文的速度递增。我们也可以为用户提供个性化、定制化的学者数据。欢迎来电咨询!咨询电话:010-8811{复制后删除}0370

www.globalauthorid.com

TOP

Copyright © 2019-2024 北京同舟云网络信息技术有限公司
京公网安备11010802033243号  京ICP备18003416号-3