Abstract
AbstractIn Part I of this paper (Ketland in Logica Universalis 14:357–381, 2020), I assumed we begin with a (relational) signature $$P = \{P_i\}$$
P
=
{
P
i
}
and the corresponding language $$L_P$$
L
P
, and introduced the following notions: a definition system$$d_{\Phi }$$
d
Φ
for a set of new predicate symbols $$Q_i$$
Q
i
, given by a set $$\Phi = \{\phi _i\}$$
Φ
=
{
ϕ
i
}
of defining $$L_P$$
L
P
-formulas (these definitions have the form: $$\forall \overline{x}(Q_i(x) \leftrightarrow \phi _i)$$
∀
x
¯
(
Q
i
(
x
)
↔
ϕ
i
)
); a corresponding translation function$$\tau _{\Phi }: L_Q \rightarrow L_P$$
τ
Φ
:
L
Q
→
L
P
; the corresponding definitional image operator$$D_{\Phi }$$
D
Φ
, applicable to $$L_P$$
L
P
-structures and $$L_P$$
L
P
-theories; and the notion of definitional equivalence itself: for structures $$A + d_{\Phi } \equiv B + d_{\Theta }$$
A
+
d
Φ
≡
B
+
d
Θ
; for theories, $$T_1 + d_{\Phi } \equiv T_2 + d_{\Theta }$$
T
1
+
d
Φ
≡
T
2
+
d
Θ
. Some results relating these notions were given, ending with two characterizations for definitional equivalence. In this second part, we explain the notion of a representation basis. Suppose a set $$\Phi = \{\phi _i\}$$
Φ
=
{
ϕ
i
}
of $$L_P$$
L
P
-formulas is given, and $$\Theta = \{\theta _i\}$$
Θ
=
{
θ
i
}
is a set of $$L_Q$$
L
Q
-formulas. Then the original set $$\Phi $$
Φ
is called a representation basis for an $$L_P$$
L
P
-structure A with inverse $$\Theta $$
Θ
iff an inverse explicit definition $$\forall \overline{x}(P_i(\overline{x}) \leftrightarrow \theta _i)$$
∀
x
¯
(
P
i
(
x
¯
)
↔
θ
i
)
is true in $$A + d_{\Phi }$$
A
+
d
Φ
, for each $$P_i$$
P
i
. Similarly, the set $$\Phi $$
Φ
is called a representation basis for a $$L_P$$
L
P
-theory T with inverse $$\Theta $$
Θ
iff each explicit definition $$\forall \overline{x}(P_i(\overline{x}) \leftrightarrow \theta _i)$$
∀
x
¯
(
P
i
(
x
¯
)
↔
θ
i
)
is provable in $$T + d_{\Phi }$$
T
+
d
Φ
. Some results about representation bases, the mappings they induce and their relationship with the notion of definitional equivalence are given. In particular, we show that $$T_1$$
T
1
(in $$L_P$$
L
P
) is definitionally equivalent to $$T_2$$
T
2
(in $$L_Q$$
L
Q
), with respect to $$\Phi $$
Φ
and $$\Theta $$
Θ
, if and only if $$\Phi $$
Φ
is a representation basis for $$T_1$$
T
1
with inverse $$\Theta $$
Θ
and $$T_2 \equiv D_{\Phi }T_1$$
T
2
≡
D
Φ
T
1
.
Publisher
Springer Science and Business Media LLC
Subject
Applied Mathematics,Logic
Reference8 articles.
1. Andréka, H., Madarász, J.X., Németi, I.: Mutual definability does not imply definitional equivalence, a simple example. Math. Log. Quart. 51(6), 591–597 (2005)
2. Andréka, H., Németi, I.: Definability Theory Course Notes. https://old.renyi.hu/pub/algebraic-logic/DefThNotes0828.pdf. (2014)
3. Goodman, N.: Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Athlone Press, London (1954)
4. Ketland, J.: Bases for structures and theories I. Logica Universalis 14, 357–381 (2020)
5. Miller, D.W.: On popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 25, 166–177 (1974)