Conservation of Energy: Missing Features in Its Nature and Justification and Why They Matter

Author:

Pitts J. BrianORCID

Abstract

AbstractMisconceptions about energy conservation abound due to the gap between physics and secondary school chemistry. This paper surveys this difference and its relevance to the 1690s–2010s Leibnizian argument that mind-body interaction is impossible due to conservation laws. Justifications for energy conservation are partly empirical, such as Joule’s paddle wheel experiment, and partly theoretical, such as Lagrange’s statement in 1811 that energy is conserved if the potential energy does not depend on time. In 1918 Noether generalized results like Lagrange’s and proved a converse: symmetries imply conservation laws and vice versa. Conservation holds if and only if nature is uniform. The rise of field physics during the 1860s–1920s implied that energy is located in particular places and conservation is primordially local: energy cannot disappear in Cambridge and reappear in Lincoln instantaneously or later; neither can it simply disappear in Cambridge or simply appear in Lincoln. A global conservation law can be inferred in some circumstances. Einstein’s General Relativity, which stimulated Noether’s work, is another source of difficulty for conservation laws. As is too rarely realized, the theory admits conserved quantities due to symmetries of the Lagrangian, like other theories. Indeed General Relativity has more symmetries and hence (at least formally) more conserved energies. An argument akin to Leibniz’s finally gets some force. While the mathematics is too advanced for secondary school, the ideas that conservation is tied to uniformities of nature and that energy is in particular places, are accessible. Improved science teaching would serve the truth and enhance the social credibility of science.

Funder

John Templeton Foundation

Publisher

Springer Science and Business Media LLC

Subject

History and Philosophy of Science,Multidisciplinary

Reference158 articles.

1. Alexander, H. G. (Ed.). (1956). The Leibniz–Clarke correspondence. Manchester: Manchester University.

2. Anderson, J. L. (1967). Principles of relativity physics. New York: Academic.

3. Arana, J. (1993 (1994)). Los científicos de la Ilustración como apologistas del Cristianismo: Albrecht von Haller y Leonhard Euler. Fragmentos de Filosofía, 3, 7–21.

4. Averill, E., & Keating, B. F. (1981). Does interactionism violate a law of classical physics? Mind: A Quarterly Review of Philosophy, 90, 102–107.

5. Banerjee, N., & Sen, S. (1997). Einstein pseudotensor and total energy of the universe. Pramana, Journal of Physics, 49, 609–615.

Cited by 6 articles. 订阅此论文施引文献 订阅此论文施引文献,注册后可以免费订阅5篇论文的施引文献,订阅后可以查看论文全部施引文献

1. Spacetime Conventionalism Revisited;Philosophy of Science;2023-08-11

2. Does Physics Forbid Libertarian Freedom?;Filozoficzne Aspekty Genezy;2022-06-16

3. Is Prime Matter Energy?;Australasian Journal of Philosophy;2022-01-12

4. COVID-19 Diagnosis by Wavelet Entropy and Particle Swarm Optimization;Intelligent Computing Theories and Application;2022

5. On Two Slights to Noether’s First Theorem: Mental Causation and General Relativity;Rethinking the Concept of Law of Nature;2022

同舟云学术

1.学者识别学者识别

2.学术分析学术分析

3.人才评估人才评估

"同舟云学术"是以全球学者为主线,采集、加工和组织学术论文而形成的新型学术文献查询和分析系统,可以对全球学者进行文献检索和人才价值评估。用户可以通过关注某些学科领域的顶尖人物而持续追踪该领域的学科进展和研究前沿。经过近期的数据扩容,当前同舟云学术共收录了国内外主流学术期刊6万余种,收集的期刊论文及会议论文总量共计约1.5亿篇,并以每天添加12000余篇中外论文的速度递增。我们也可以为用户提供个性化、定制化的学者数据。欢迎来电咨询!咨询电话:010-8811{复制后删除}0370

www.globalauthorid.com

TOP

Copyright © 2019-2024 北京同舟云网络信息技术有限公司
京公网安备11010802033243号  京ICP备18003416号-3